In defense of the contradictions implied by the theory of common grace
and of the well-meant offer (or “free offer”), contemporary theologians appeal
to what they call “paradoxes” found elsewhere in Scriptures. Some of them are
discussed and responded to below. Their argument is that if we accept these
other paradoxes (as they call them), why can’t we just call the contradictions
of common grace “paradoxes” also, and simply (in humility) just accept them.
(A) God’s Sovereignty and Human Responsibility
Herman Hoeksema (1886-1965):
The question is
whether there is a real or apparent contradiction involved in the truth of
God’s sovereignty and man’s responsibility.
Let us put both
truths in propositional form:
(1) God is
absolutely sovereign even so that he determines the moral acts of man, both
good and evil.
(2) Man is
responsible before God for all his moral acts.
Now, the
question is not whether there is a problem here. It may well be that we cannot
answer the question how God is able
to determine man’s deeds without destroying man’s responsibility. That he is
able to do so is asserted plainly by the two propositions stated above. But
whether or not we can understand this operation of the sovereign God upon man
is not the question. The sole question is whether the two propositions
concerning God’s sovereignty and man’s responsibility are contradictory. This
we deny. In fact, they cannot possibly be, for the simple reason that they
assert something about two wholly different subjects.
They would be
contradictory if the first proposition denied what is affirmed in the second.
But this is not true. The first proposition asserts something about God: He is
absolutely sovereign and determines the acts of man. The second proposition
predicates something about man: He is responsible for his moral acts. Does the
first proposition deny that man is responsible? If it does you have here a
contradiction. But it does not. Those who like to discover a contradiction
here, usually the enemies of the truth of God’s sovereignty, simply take for
granted that to assert that God is sovereign even over man’s acts is to say the
same as that man is not responsible. It must be pointed out, however, that this
is neither expressed nor implied in the first proposition. In the two
propositions responsibility is not both affirmed and denied at the same time to
man.
The two
propositions would, of course, also be contradictory if the second proposition
denied what is affirmed in the first. In that case, sovereignty even over the
acts of man would be both affirmed and denied to God. But also this is neither
expressed nor implied in the two propositions, unless it can first be shown
conclusively that to say that man is responsible is the same as declaring that
God is not sovereign over his moral acts. And this has never been demonstrated,
nor is it self-evident.
If they were
really contradictory they could not both be the object of the Christian’s
faith. We could only conclude that either the one or the other were not true.
Now, however,
since they involve no contradictions, and since both are clearly revealed in Scripture,
we accept both, whether or not we can combine them into one concept.
And the attempt
to do so, to solve the problem, must be considered laudable.
What pastor has
not confronted the necessity, in his catechism classes, to answer a question
concerning this problem when he was instructing his pupils in the truth of
God’s immutable decrees? And what instructor was satisfied to reply to his
earnest inquiring pupil that here we face a contradiction?
To me it would
seem that the solution of the problem, as far as Reformed theology is
concerned, must be sought in the direction of properly defining man’s
responsibility. If the question is asked how a divinely determined creature can
be responsible for his acts, it stands to reason that his freedom and responsibility
must be defined as falling within the compass of God’s decrees and sovereignty.
Man’s freedom is a creaturely, and, therefore a dependent freedom. And so is
his responsibility.
(Source: The Clark-Van Til Controversy [The Trinity Foundation, 2005], pp.
38-39)
(B) The Trinity
David J. Engelsma:
The familiar appeal … to the oneness and
threeness of God’s being [in support of the inconsistencies implied by common
grace and the well-meant offer], as though the oneness and threeness of the
being of God are also contradiction is a complete failure. For God is not one and three in the same
respect. He is one in being, and three in persons. The Trinity of
God is not a glaring contradiction. The doctrine of the Trinity reveals God as
incomprehensible. It does not reveal Him as nonsense.
(Source: PRTJ, vol. 53, no. 1 [Nov.
2019], p. 102)
It is part of
our defence of the denial of the offer that we take the offensive against the
offer. We charge that the offer involves a Calvinist in sheer contradiction.
That God is gracious only to some in predestination, but gracious to all in the
gospel, and that God wills only some to be saved in predestination but wills
all to be saved by the gospel, is flat, irreconcilable contradiction. It is not
paradox, but contradiction. I speak reverently: God Himself cannot reconcile
these teachings. Nor is there any similarity between this contradiction and the
truth of the Trinity that surpasses our understanding. The truth of the Trinity
is not contradictory, for it holds that God is one in being and three in
persons, not, therefore, one and three in the very same respects.
(Source: Pamphlet:
Is Denial of the “Well-Meant Offer”
Hyper-Calvinism?)
Robert
L. Reymond (1932-2013):
But does not the
classical doctrine of the Trinity present, if not a real contradiction, at
least an apparent one? The widely acclaimed “paradox” of the Trinity—namely,
that three equals one and one equals three—is in fact not one at all. If the
numerical adjectives “one” and “three” are intended to describe in both cases
the same noun so that the theologian intends to say that one God equals three
Gods and three Gods equal one God in the same way that one might say that one
apple numerically equals three apples and three apples numerically equal one
apple, this is not an apparent contradiction or paradox. This is a real
contradiction which not even God can resolve! Nor would he even try to do so!
But this is not what the church teaches by its doctrine of the Trinity,
although this representation is advanced all too often not only by lay people
but also by good theologians. For example, rejecting the traditional
distinction that God is one in one sense (essence) and three in another sense
(persons), Van Til writes:
God
is a one-conscious being, and yet he
is a three-conscious being … the work ascribed to any of the persons is the
work of one absolute person … It is
sometimes asserted that we can prove to men that we are not asserting anything
that they ought to consider irrational, inasmuch as we say that God is one in
essence and three in person. We therefore claim that we have not asserted unity
and trinity of exactly the same thing.
Yet
this is not the whole truth of the matter. We
do assert that God, that is, the whole Godhead, is one person … within the
ontological Trinity we must maintain that God is numerically one. He is one person … Yet, within the being of the one person we are
permitted and compelled by Scripture to make the distinction between a specific
or generic type of being, and three
personal subsistences.32
But no orthodox
creed has ever so represented the doctrine. In fact, it is apparent that all of
the historic creeds of the church have been exceedingly jealous to avoid the
very appearance of contradiction here by employing one noun—“God” or
“Godhead”—with the numerical “one” and another noun—“persons”—with the numeral
“three.” The church has never taught that three Gods are one God or that one
person is three persons but rather that “in the unity of the Godhead there are
three persons” (Westminster Confession of Faith, II/iii), the Father, the Son,
and the Holy Spirit, and that while each is wholly and essentially divine, no
one person totally comprehends all that the Godhead is hypostatically.
Certainly some of the divine attributes which insure the unity of the Godhead
may be unknown to us. But when the Bible refers to the Father and the Son and
the Holy Spirit, it intends that we think of three persons, that is, three
hypostatically distinct centers of self-consciousness within the Godhead,
whereas when it employs the imprecise and flexible title “God,” it refers
either to the Godhead construed in their unitary wholeness (for example, Gen.
1:26) or to one of the persons of the Godhead, specifically which one to be
determined by the context (for example, “God” in Rom. 8:28 refers to the Father
while “God” in Rom. 9:5 refers to the Son). Thus construed, the doctrine of the
Trinity does not confront us with even an apparent contradiction, much less a
real one. The Triune God is a complex
Being but not a contradiction!
(Source: A New Systematic Theology of the Christian
Faith, [1998] pp. 108-109)
(C) The Hypostatic Union of the Divine and Human Natures
in the Person of Christ
Robert
L. Reymond (1932-2013):
[The] Christian
church has never creedally declared that Christ is one person and also two
persons or one nature and also two natures. Rather, the church has declared
that the Lord Jesus Christ, “being the eternal Son of God, became man, and so
was and continues to be God and man, in two distinct natures and one person
forever” (Westminster Shorter Catechism, Question 21). Note again: Christ is
one person possessing the full complex of divine attributes and the full
complex of human attributes. Christ is complex, surely, but he is not a
contradiction!
(Source: A New Systematic Theology of the Christian
Faith [1998], p. 109)
No comments:
Post a Comment